This online colloquium has been established to discuss Sandra Leonie Field’s recent book, Potentia: Hobbes and Spinoza on Power and Popular Politics. We began with an introduction to the text, followed by responses from Alissa MacMillan, Christopher Holman and Justin Steinberg. We conclude this week with a reply by Sandra Leonie Field. Many thanks to Oxford University Press for supporting this colloquium.
***
It is a great honour to have my book
featured by the European Hobbes Society, and to have Alissa MacMillan, Chris
Holman, and Justin Steinberg give such detailed attention to the book’s ideas
and arguments.
Potentia
aspires to make contributions both to studies of Hobbes and Spinoza, and to
democratic theory. I hope to have achieved philosophical and philological
rigour in my readings of Hobbes’s and Spinoza’s texts. At the same time, my
purpose in those readings is to locate ideas which might help reorient us with
respect to contemporary systematic questions of political philosophy. I thank
my critics for pressing on both of these fronts. I’ll respond to four areas of
concern that they raise: (i) Hobbes on power; (ii) Hobbes on democracy; (iii) the
Hobbes/Spinoza relation; and (iv) the larger lessons for democratic theory.[1]
i. Hobbes on Power
My interpretation of Hobbes centres on
identifying a shift in his conception of human power, both individual and
collective, between his early and late political texts. I draw significant
political consequences from this shift. I would like to thank MacMillan for her
efforts to reconstitute and situate this shift in terms of debates regarding
the Hobbesian individual. Her presentation conveys some of the excitement that
I myself felt in carrying out this research, excitement which I feared may have
been lost in all the finer scholarly details of the chapters. Equally, however,
I would like to thank Steinberg for asking whether I have overstated the
shift’s political consequences.[2] In
particular, Steinberg expresses skepticism that the changing conception of
power explains (a) why Hobbes abandons De Cive’s ‘sleeping sovereign’ in
Leviathan, or (b) why in his early works Hobbes underestimates the
threat of informal collectivities to sovereign power. I’ll address these two
challenges in turn.
Steinberg reconstitutes my argument against
the sleeping sovereign as follows. The sleeping sovereign does not actively
exercise its power most of the time. But the later text Leviathan
conceives power (potentia) as efficacy. An inactive power is
ineffective, and as such, it is no power at all. So, the sleeping sovereign
lacks power and is not viable as a sovereign.
To this argument, Steinberg objects that
nothing about efficacy requires continual action. Even once we clear out any
residual scholastic commitment to inner essential tendencies, there must be a
way of talking about everyday tendencies or dispositions or inactive powers.
For instance, surely we can say that a driver has the power to brake even when
they don’t exercise that power. Just like the driver ready to brake, surely a
sleeping sovereign could be ready to issue directives. Inactivity does not mean
lack of power.
In response, I grant that it is possible
for Hobbes, in his later non-scholastic conception of power, to speak of
dispositions and inactive powers. But under what conditions? For Hobbes,
everything has its determinate causes, and possibility relates only to our
epistemic limitations. Thus, to say that something is possible is just to say
that, for all we know, it may happen in the future. Correspondingly, we can
attribute powers (potentiae) or dispositions only to the extent that we
anticipate likely future efficacy, as for instance in the case of the car
driver’s power to
brake (52–53).[3]
Nonetheless, I would suggest that this very
standard of likely future efficacy raises problems for the putative power (potentia)
of a sleeping sovereign that it does not raise for the driver’s power to brake.
Recall what is at stake: a government covers quotidian administration and
governance, but from time to time the sleeping sovereign wakes, holding the
government to account or redirecting its work through a vote. The sleeping
sovereign, qua sovereign (summa potestas), holds the entitlement to
everyone’s obedience. Imagine the sovereign makes a ruling which is not to the
pleasure of the government. How can it be confident of achieving the concrete
obedience of the populace? Hobbes’s answer in his early texts is simple: the
sovereign is entitled to obedience, and the sovereign will get that obedience,
because it holds the sword. But what is this ‘sword’, how is it constituted?
Let us consider this power, not as a matter of entitlement, but as a question
of concrete efficacy. It is composed out of the actions of individuals in
society, which in turn are shaped by the everyday incentives and pressures that
they face within ongoing relationships. And here lies the problem: subjects’
everyday actions follow patterns of obedience to the government. If some
portion of the government and/or the populace choose not to comply with the
sovereign, they have the ready network of collective power to do so. We end up
with divided allegiance and risk of war, and a serious question mark over the
likely future efficacy (and hence power) of the sovereign. Under an alternative
scenario, the sleeping sovereign, aware of this risk, might take a strategy of
appeasement: taking care not to ask controversial questions or allow
controversial responses. On this scenario, a sleeping sovereign may avert the
risk of civil war, but the scenario is hardly more encouraging for the idea
that the sleeping sovereign is the true seat of power (95–98).
Let me turn now to the second respect in
which Steinberg is skeptical about the political impact of Hobbes’s changing
philosophical conception of power: concerning the political salience of
informal groupings. Steinberg reconstitutes my argument as follows. On Hobbes’s
early view, power potentia is conceived in a scholastic manner as
grounded in essences, and only genuine individuals–not mere aggregates–can bear
essences. This means that informal groupings, lacking potestas and
formal structure, cannot bear essences or have power. This in turn leads Hobbes
to underestimate their capacity to destabilize the sovereign.
To this argument, Steinberg objects that
Hobbes is in fact critical of essences. For instance, Hobbes’s early discussion
of human nature as a sum of various powers amounts to an antischolastic and antiessentialising
reduction of the concept of human nature. So, even for early Hobbes, ‘we don’t
need a theory of essences and their bearers in order to determine what sorts of
things have powers’.
In response, I concede that Hobbes is
attempting an antischolastic polemic on multiple conceptual fronts, right from
his early works. But my point is that, regardless of the vigour with which
Hobbes may depart from scholasticism in many respects, there are conceptual
features remaining in his early view of powers which are illuminatingly viewed
as scholastic legacies. For Hobbes in his early works, collective power (potestas)
is conceived of as the sum of the powers (potentiae) of the individual
members of the collective, the full use of which the collective is entitled by
(actual or rationally imputed) contract; the power potentia of the
collective is equated to its potestas. Correspondingly, in these early
works, Hobbes vigorously refuses to attribute to informal collectivities any
power (certainly not potestas, but also not potentia) of their
own (57–73). To me, this seems
to show, contra Steinberg, that Hobbes does in fact ‘rely on a theory of
essences and their bearers in order to determine what sorts of things have
power.’ It is this reliance that (I argue) contributes to Hobbes’s early blind
spot about the threat of informal collectivities. To be sure, Hobbes is aware
and concerned about the threat of insurrection throughout his entire oeuvre.
But it is striking to me that Hobbes, in his early works, attempts to conceive
seditious groupings as illicit formal collectivities, leading (I argue) to a
straitened and inadequate grasp of the dynamics of popular unrest (73–77, 100–104).
ii. Hobbes on Democracy
Following its analysis of Hobbesian
concepts of power, Potentia articulates a certain understanding of
Hobbesian democracy. As already discussed above, I think that the ‘sleeping
sovereign’ model of democracy is deeply flawed, and that it is Hobbes’s own recognition
of these flaws that leads him to abandon the model in his later writings. In
its place, I offer my model of ‘repressive egalitarianism’, which draws both on
my own conceptual and exegetical analyses of power in Hobbes’s later writings,
and also on more historically informed studies of Collins and Zagorin.
According to this model, the key to democratic sovereignty is maximal
suppression of sub-state power blocs, such that individuals are rendered equal
in power to one another, and unable to band together to disrupt the sovereign
democratic decision (127–139).
To be clear, in my discussions of repressive egalitarianism, it is not my
purpose to defend repressive egalitarianism as an optimal model of popular
power, but merely to defend the exegetical claim that it is Hobbes’s model. In
the arc of the book’s argument, the value in Hobbesian repressive
egalitarianism is its withering intolerance towards the oligarchic informal
forces in the social body which so often masquerade as bearers of popular power.
For now, I’ll consider three objections to my interpretation of Hobbes on
democracy, two from Holman and one from MacMillan.
Holman’s first objection is that repressive
egalitarianism is far from the most interesting or salient model of democracy
that we might glean from Hobbes’s texts. My model of repressive egalitarianism
appears implicitly committed to electoral democracy. But in Holman’s view,
Hobbes’s model of democracy is neither plebiscitary (as per Tuck), nor
electoral/representative, but direct participatory democracy. Holman constructs
this Rousseauvian reading of Hobbes by drawing on De Cive’s definition
of democracy as an assembly of all citizens.[4] On
Holman’s reading, this democracy requires ‘concrete institutional spaces’ for
shared deliberation that are ‘universally accessible and must meet at
determinate–as opposed to merely occasional–times and places’. In this light,
my book should be faulted for missing what is both the true Hobbesian model of
democracy, and also a more useful model for us today, instead wilfully
promoting a less meaningfully democratic model.
For now, my response will focus on Holman’s
claims regarding Hobbes’s texts, leaving the contemporary application to be
considered in my following section. I confess I am skeptical regarding the
Hobbesian credentials of Holman’s model. Within De Cive, a democratic
assembly, an assembly of all citizens, is an assembly in which ‘everyone has a
right’ to vote and participate in debates. But there is no indication that he
views a small (relative to population) assembly like a parliament as being in principle
disqualified from meeting this requirement. Indeed, as sovereignty is vested in
a single assembly, actual participation must be limited to a small number by
logistical necessity. Certainly, as Holman points out, Hobbes argues that
England of the Rump Parliament was an oligarchy and not a democracy. But what
makes this the case is not (contra Holman) the general fact that parliaments
are relatively small and inaccessible bodies, but the much more specific fact
that this parliament had permanently and formally excluded some people on the
basis of their political views (in the course of the 1648–9 transition between Long and
Rump Parliaments).[5]
If I am right, De Cive offers a
model of democracy which is content with only very limited actual
participation. Holman and Tuck both, in different ways, try to resist this
conclusion, and Holman’s proposal strikes me as just as creative as Tuck’s.
Tuck’s plebiscitary democratic sovereignty achieves universality by dropping
the requirement for holding an actual assembly. Holman’s alternative envisages
multiple deliberative assemblies jointly covering the entire commonwealth. But
in its creativity, Holman’s proposal seems to me to stray further away from
anything Hobbes could endorse: for what better way to commit the cardinal
Hobbesian sin of inviting conflict through ambiguity of authority than by
sanctioning multiple mutually insubordinate regional assemblies.
In my account of Hobbes’s late models of
political order, repressive egalitarianism is a general feature of all forms of
sovereignty. Whether democracy, aristocracy, or monarchy, the important thing
is that there should be as little as possible by way of counter-powers which
could challenge sovereign commands. Rather, the commonwealth should aggregate
isolated individuals who have little choice but compliance with sovereign
command. But repressive egalitarianism would take a particular manifestation in
democratic orders. One key risk to be addressed is that democratic assemblies
themselves might be sites for the formation of informal oligarchic power blocs
and oligarchic allegiance. I argue that Hobbes’s analysis of counsel shows a
simultaneous commitment to widespread consultation across the whole population
along with a strong hostility to collective deliberation within political
assembly (especially democratic assembly) (124–127).
Holman’s second objection is that I have
underplayed Hobbes’s account of the possibilities of non-antagonistic
sociality, found for instance in Leviathan Chapter 22’s discussion of
collective activities. In response, I grant that my presentation has focussed
more heavily on informal oligarchic power blocs, such as may accumulate around
rich or charismatic figures. These are not antagonistic–their complex structure
eludes any simple binary of horizontal mutual association versus vertical
domination–but nor are they very appealing. I focus on these because they are
(I argue) both underrecognized in the literature, and of great systematic
importance in understanding Hobbes’s later political philosophy.
Despite this focus, I do not mean to deny
that Hobbes grants there can also be more productive and collaborative
sociality. But to me, the key questions are, what are the concrete conditions
under which such sociality arises and is sustained? and what is its relation to
politics? Answering these questions reveals that in Hobbes’s philosophy, the
human possibility of productive sociality can neither serve as a model nor as a
foundation for democratic politics. In Leviathan’s Chapter 22, on
‘systemes’, Holman’s exemplars of sociable association occur within, and
presuppose, the security provided by sovereign rule. As such, they cannot serve
as a model for that rule. Furthermore, I don’t see in Hobbes any trace of the
idea that these associations could, even when internally sociable, play a
useful role in shaping or constraining sovereign power. (That idea, which I
endorse, I associate with Spinoza, not Hobbes (260–261).) To the contrary, on my reading, all associations constitute
threats to sovereign rule, because they constitute points of incipient
resistance to that rule. In laying out idea of ‘repressive egalitarianism’, my
point is to trace as best I can Hobbes’s own late account of the conditions of
possibility of overcoming the political problem, which is to constitute a
unified commonwealth without internal power blocs. As it is impossible to
eliminate internal power blocs entirely, I read Chapter 22 as an attempt to
taxonomize and triage the threat posed by those groupings that remain.
Now I turn to MacMillan, who objects that I
soft-pedal the educational dimension of both Hobbes’s and Spinoza’s political
philosophies. MacMillan suggests that repressive egalitarianism is achieved
through rational education, and not through any ‘strange and impossible
engineering of individuals’. Drawing on Pettit’s work, she suggests that
subjects can come to internalize and act upon their duty in good part through
achieving a true understanding of the grounds of politics, and not merely
through indoctrination.
In response, the book does attempt a
discussion of Hobbes’s views on education. But perhaps this is unsatisfying to
MacMillan, because the upshot of that discussion is a fairly deep ambivalence
regarding the promise of education to solve the political problem. In Hobbes’s
early works, I argue that neither education nor indoctrination are particularly
important. For he is confident peace can be secured simply by establishing the
appropriate juridical regime of rights, with subjects’ compliance achieved by
the threat of the sovereign’s sword, not by their understanding (73–77, 108–112). In the later works,
Hobbes is more attentive to the insufficiency of the threat of punishment to
shape behaviour, leading to a much greater interest in persuading and teaching
people how they ought to behave (98–106, 112–118). But on my interpretation, the real underlying problem is that
subjects can have hope of success in resisting sovereign commands, if they ally
themselves with informal oligarchic power blocs beneath the sovereign.
Hobbesian repressive egalitarianism seeks to break up or constrain potential
counterpowers in the social body. For Hobbes, intellectual strategies of
education or indoctrination, while not without some value, cannot succeed
unless they are paired with this more structural approach to political
stability (140–141).
iii.
The Hobbes/Spinoza Relation
One ambition of the book is to reconfigure
our understanding of the relation between the political philosophies of Hobbes
and Spinoza, which I think has been greatly muddied by the absence of a clear
account of their various conceptions of power. Potentia claims to
establish a reading which shows their political philosophies have more in
common than usually recognized. In particular, I draw out the similarities
between (late) Hobbesian potentia and Spinoza’s potentia operandi,
and their shared focus on the concrete conditions the durability of the state.
Steinberg raises the concern that I have
overdrawn the similarities between the two thinkers, and unduly minimized
breaks of real significance between them. Specifically, even if we grant the
similarity between late Hobbes’s potentia and Spinoza’s potentia
operandi, they ‘each have an additional conception of power that the other
would have rejected (or did reject)’. First, Spinoza rejects appeals to de
jure authority and obligation, whereas such concepts are the foundation of
Hobbesian philosophy. Second, Hobbes offers no counterpart to the Spinozist potentia
agendi, power of producing effects understood through the thing’s own
nature alone.
In response, I very much like Steinberg’s
neat characterization of what I concede is a deep difference between the
thinkers. Nonetheless, I wonder whether that deep difference needs somehow to
be accommodated more in the book than it already is, given the book’s goals.
The observation that Hobbes has a strongly
juridical conception of power, and that Spinoza critiques Hobbes for this
conception, is central to the book. A major challenge for the book is to
determine what this difference amounts to. The view that a Spinozist attention
to the question of potentia as efficacy is sufficient to undermine
Hobbes’s supposedly hard-headed civil science is a staple of the literature.
According to this view (encouraged by Spinoza’s own Letter 50 and by Chapter 17
of his Theological-Political Treatise), Hobbes’s juridical focus on
questions of right and authority comes at the expense of any serious
consideration of the concrete grounds of exercise of this right. But in fact
(still according to this view), Hobbesian absolute sovereignty cannot achieve
requisite potentia to match its authority. Thus Hobbes’s political philosophy is a failure (151–156).
The first half of the book strives to show
that this view is false. I show that Hobbes in his later works very clearly
does have an account of the potentia requisite to sovereign potestas.
In particular, adequate potentia can be achieved in the regime, so
ambivalent to contemporary sensibilities, that I have characterized as
‘repressive egalitarian’. In reconstructing the late Hobbesian theory of potentia,
and giving it such relative prominence in the book, I am fighting against a
tide of literature which (from the Hobbes side) pays too little attention to
Hobbes’s nonjuridical analysis of power, and which (correspondingly, from the
Spinoza side) critiques Hobbes for his neglect of such an analysis.
Thus, despite the book’s focus on Hobbes’s potentia,
in no way do I mean thereby to deny the obvious fact that that Hobbes is
overwhelmingly, from start to finish, a juridical thinker of power, focussed on
questions of right and potestas. At the same time, I confess I am rather
more interested in Hobbes’s concrete theory of power than in his juridical
theory. I agree with Hoekstra’s suggestion that juridically conceived absolute
sovereignty ultimately ‘becomes a kind of hidden God, largely irrelevant to our
ongoing thinking about politics’.[6]
And if the goal is obtaining a solid grasp of concrete political power and its
possible configurations, Spinoza’s own picture is sometimes naive and
simplistic (notably the Theological-Political Treatise’s discussions of
democracy, Chapters 5 and 16). On this point, our understanding is richly
enhanced by Hobbes’s theory of potentia.
I turn now to consider Spinoza’s potentia
agendi. In his own work, Steinberg convincingly shows that the Spinozist
goal of politics is freedom in a metaphysical sense, that is, the increasing
rational self-determination of citizens, understood in terms of an increase of
their individual potentiae agendi. By contrast, Hobbes is remarkable
amongst philosophers for his total lack of interest in specifying ethical virtues,
or indeed in any ethical conception of happiness beyond political salience, and
also for his vehemently antimetaphysical disinterest in question of natures.
I already do recognize Spinoza’s potentia
agendi has some role in core political theses of the book which would not
have been possible from Hobbes alone. I already grant that the model of popular
power that I end up championing is neo-Spinozist insofar as it is interested in
specifying a political order’s own power (its potentia agendi), and not merely
its efficacy (237–238). I also criticize
Hobbes for his failure to consider that the seditious character of sub-state
groups may be a product of certain conditions rather than a constant of human
nature, and this failure on Hobbes’s part is conceivably linked to his general
lack of interest in philosophically investigating human nature (260–261). What more exactly, salient to
the goals of the book, should I have acknowledged?[7]
iv. Larger Lessons for Democratic Theory
In this final section of reply, I address
some concerns raised regarding Potentia’s contributions to contemporary
democratic theory. Holman and MacMillan both defend the honour of democratic
radicalism and of grassroots power, which they suggest is insufficiently
respected in my book.
The question, ‘what does popular power even
mean?’, can be met with two quite different kinds of answer. One kind of answer
analyzes the conceptual structure of popular power. A different kind of answer
specifies the implementation of power so conceived. Potentia is
primarily concerned to defend an answer of the first, conceptual, type. I
propose to reconceive popular power, such that a political phenomenon counts as
a manifestation of popular power when it is popular (it eliminates oligarchy
and encompasses the whole polity) and powerful (it robustly determines
political and social outcomes). Let me draw out two notable features of this
conception. First, popular power is judged at the level of the overall
functioning of society, rather than at the level of specific events, processes,
or institutions. Second, popular power is judged at the level of durably
achieved effects, not at the level of will or intention. If we want popular
power worthy of the name, this is what I take it to consist in. If this
conceptual move is granted, then the second type of question does become
pressing: what specific political phenomena, events, and processes might tend
to be found in a society meeting this standard of popular power? However, Potentia
does not offer a fully formed answer to this second question, instead just
offering some schematic suggestions (252–262).
Thus, it is a misconception that Potentia
is importantly opposed to various democratic phenomena of a more radical
flavour (plebiscites, social movements, or even participatory democracy); it is
a misconception that I think it is a mistake for social movements, mass
plebiscites, or other mass participation to be central to popular politics. The
conceptual frame that I advance simply denies that any particular phenomenon,
including plebiscites or social movements, is the definitive bearer or gauge of
popular power. In principle, I am quite open about whether in fact a society of
popular power will feature extensive plebiscites and/or social movements.
In fact, I am sympathetic to the idea that
some significant presence of social movements would be required for meaningful
popular power to be achieved (258–262).
As Machiavelli argues, peaceful republics tend to be aristocratic (like Venice);
to achieve a less hierarchical polity, contentious politics is necessary (like
the tumults of the Roman plebs).[8] It
is true that I am more skeptical about plebiscites: historical examples both
from my native Australia and from my current residence of Singapore show how
readily plebiscites can be engineered to serve purposes of authorities who
establish them; in other cases, the results of the vote have been captured by
the deep pockets of partisan advertising (137, n61–62). At the same time, sometimes plebiscites have been established in
more meaningful ways. One of the better examples is the Irish Abortion
Referendum. The Irish Citizen’s Assembly looms large in the book because of its
role in setting up that referendum, not because some such assembly is
necessarily the keystone of popular power (256).
So, with these general comments in place,
let me turn to my critics. MacMillan accepts my critique of any radical
democratic appeal to a popular power standing outside the processes of social
formation. But in her critical comments, she suggests that I go too far in the
institutional direction. In the web of mutual causation between institutions
and the individuals who interact with them, if it’s a choice where to locate
popular power, MacMillan interprets my book as identifying popular power on the
side of the institutions. On her reading, I grant that social movements have a
causal impact on the institutions of popular power, but deny that these
movements are themselves part of popular power. MacMillan proposes that we
should resist this such a stark choice, and instead we should view popular
power as a ‘symbiosis’ between grassroots action and institutions.
In response, the view I want to defend is
in fact aligned rather closely with MacMillan’s. Perhaps I introduced confusion
by a carelessly equivocal use of the notion of ‘institutional’. Sometimes the
term contrasts with ‘extrainstitutional’ forces such as social movements and
informal collective actions, but other times ‘institutional’ is understood more
expansively, to include the full array of social practices and processes which
together constitute the polity. On my view, popular power should be identified
at the second, broader, level, and this sounds very much like MacMillan’s ‘symbiosis’.
Now I turn to Holman’s comments on the
book’s contemporary claims. Holman agrees that it is not worth defending a
radical democracy founded (as per Tuck and Negri) on the unmediated will of the
people. But in Holman’s view, I am too quick to offer parliamentary democracy
as an alternative. Instead, Holman defends another radical tradition, for which
the core commitment is a critique of the elitism of representative democracy.
In response, I am happy to acknowledge the
countless perversities of representative democracy, not merely its
aristocratic/oligarchic tendencies, but also its systematic distortion by
electoral objectives (254–258).
At the same time, I wonder whether there remains a role for
representative systems, to help balance out some potential hidden exclusions
and difficulties that face strong interpretations of direct participatory
democracy. For instance, the extreme time-poverty of carers constitutes an
obstacle to their participation in formally open participatory assemblies. For
another example, a privilege to the autonomy of local participatory assembles
can provide cover for antidistributive policies between rich and poor regions.
Again,
most important to Potentia is the conceptual criterion of popular power.
My point is not to be either for or against particular practices or
institutions, such as electoral versus participatory democracy. What needs to
be identified is the combination of elements which best achieves a society of
equality and participation over time. In my own sketch, I imagine many factors
interacting with and counteracting electoral politics: a mix of participatory
fora, lottocracy, social movements, as well as expert bodies. But if an overall
political order which eliminates electoral representation and replaces it with
extensive participatory democracy in fact meets the standards of popular power
that I have described, I am happy to endorse it.
However, I recognize that my conceptual
claim is controversial. In particular, I suspect that Holman may not grant it. Holman’s
own discussion of democracy, both in this review and in his other work, appears
to identify popular power with a specific political location–namely, a network
of participatory deliberative fora–and not at the level of overall social
effects. This feature of Holman’s scholarship helps to make vivid the hard
choice that lies at the foundation of Potentia’s engagement with
democratic theory. The book starts by facing up to the disappointments that
afflict all particular institutions and sites of democracy–not merely electoral
democracy but equally plebiscites and mass movements, and also even
participatory democracy. From time to time, in greater or lesser degree, these
institutions and sites all find themselves going wrong. They may be captured by
moneyed interests, eroded by zerosum conflict, confidently tyrannizing their
internal minorities, wracked by an inability translate ideas into durable
outcomes. In light of these disappointments, what should we think of popular
power and democracy? Holman’s response is that popular power is highly
ambivalent and can be self-destructive: that’s just the tragedy of democracy. The
response of my book is different. Rather than hold onto a tragic vision of
democracy, and correspondingly oscillate between hope and despair about its
value, instead Potentia proposes the very meaning of popular power needs
to be rethought. On this new conceptualization, a self-destructive, oligarchic,
or otherwise failing democracy is not a case of misused popular power. Rather,
it is a case where popular power worthy of the name has not yet been achieved.
Sandra Leonie Field (Yale-NUS College)
[1] This research was supported
by Yale-NUS College (through grant number IG17-SR101).
[2] I also owe broader thanks to
Steinberg. Steinberg’s own writings on Spinoza have been very important in my
research. But on reflection, I realise that my book gives quite an unfair
characterization of his views. I look forward to setting the record straight at
some point in the future.
[3] All in-text references are to Field, Potentia.
[4] Thomas Hobbes, On the Citizen, edited and translated by
Richard Tuck and Michael Silverthorne (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2014), 7.1.
[5] Thomas Hobbes, Behemoth, or the Long Parliament, edited by
Paul Seaward (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2010), reading 319 in light of 317.
[6] Kinch Hoekstra, ‘Early Modern Absolutism and
Constitutionalism’, Cardozo Law Review, 34 (3), 2013: 1097.
[7] I think that sometimes comparisons of the two authors can be too
quick in appealing to Spinoza’s potentia agendi to illuminate his
differences from Hobbes. For instance, I am skeptical how much difference there
is between Hobbes and Spinoza on the appropriate balance of hope and fear in
their respective best regimes.
[8] Sandra Leonie Field, ‘Contentious
politics: Hobbes, Machiavelli, and corporate power’, Democracy Futures series, The
Conversation, 20 November 2015.